Continued from last week...
Solution.
Let’s begin with reconstructing the diagram:
The goal here is use these objects \(B_1\) and \(B_2\) in \(\mathcal{C}\) as the basis for constructing a new category \(\mathcal{C}_{B_1 B_2}\text{.}\)
We define an object in \(\mathcal{C}_{B_1 B_2}\) as an object of \(\mathcal{C}\) equiped with a pair of maps to \(B_1\) and \(B_2\text{.}\)
We define a map in \(\mathcal{C}_{B_1 B_2}\) as a map in \(\mathcal{C}\) which preserves the structure of the commutative diagram above. Specifically, any map \(X \xrightarrow{f} Y\) in \(\mathcal{C}_{B_1 B_2}\) must satisfy the relations \(\psi_1 f = \phi_1\) and \(\psi_2 f = \phi_2\text{.}\)
Since every \(\mathcal{C}_{B_1 B_2}\)-map comes from a map \(\mathcal{C}\text{,}\) it must have a defined domain and codomain. Likewise, since the objects in \(\mathcal{C}_{B_1 B_2}\) come from objects in \(\mathcal{C}\) they must each have an identity map. For any object \(X\) in \(\mathcal{C}_{B_1 B_2}\text{,}\) a simple substitution \(\phi_1 1_X = \phi_1\) and \(\phi_2 1_X = \phi_2\) shows the identity maps from \(\mathcal{C}\) preserve structure.
Let’s take a second to verify that \(\mathcal{C}_{B_1 B_2}\) is closed under composition. Consider two maps \(X \xrightarrow{f} Y \xrightarrow{g} Z\text{.}\)
We can assume the following relations from the definition of \(\mathcal{C}_{B_1 B_2}\)-map:
\begin{equation*}
\psi_1 f = \phi_1
\end{equation*}
\begin{equation*}
\psi_2 f = \phi_2
\end{equation*}
\begin{equation*}
\chi_1 g = \psi_1
\end{equation*}
\begin{equation*}
\chi_2 g = \psi_2
\end{equation*}
In order for \(g \circ f\) to be a valid \(\mathcal{C}_{B_1 B_2}\)-map, we need to establish both \(\chi_1 (g \circ f) = \phi_1\) and \(\chi_1 (g \circ f) = \phi_1\text{.}\) This follows easily from the associative property in \(\mathcal{C}\) and substitution with the relations above:
\begin{equation*}
\chi_1 (g \circ f) = (\chi_1 \circ g) \circ f = \psi_1 \circ f = \phi_1
\end{equation*}
\begin{equation*}
\chi_2 (g \circ f) = (\chi_2 \circ g) \circ f = \psi_2 \circ f = \phi_2
\end{equation*}
The only thing left to prove is the associative law. Let’s consider a set of three \(\mathcal{C}_{B_1 B_2}\)-maps \(A \xrightarrow{f} B \xrightarrow{g} C \xrightarrow{h} D\text{.}\) Each of these maps needs to correspond with a pair of maps to \(B_1\) and \(B_2\text{,}\) as per the following diagram:
By our definition of composition above, we know we have \(g \circ f\) satisfying \(\chi_1 (g \circ f) = \phi_1\) and \(\chi_2 (g \circ f) = \phi_2\text{.}\) Postcompose with \(h\) to get \(h \circ (g \circ f)\) with \(\omega_1 (h \circ (g \circ f)) = \chi_1 (g \circ f) = \phi_1\) and \(\omega_1 (h \circ (g \circ f)) = \chi_1 (g \circ f) = \phi_1\text{.}\)
Similarly, we must have \(h \circ g\) satisfying \(\omega_1 (h \circ g) = \psi_1\) and \(\omega_2 (h \circ g) = \psi_2\text{.}\) Precompose with \(f\) to get \((h \circ g) \circ f\) with \(\omega_1 ((h \circ g) \circ f) = (\omega_1 (h \circ g)) \circ f
= \psi_1 f = \phi_1\) and \(\omega_2 ((h \circ g) \circ f) = (\omega_2 (h \circ g)) \circ f
= \psi_2 f = \phi_2\text{.}\)
Since we know that the associative property holds in \(\mathcal{C}\) and have shown that it satisfies the structure preservation of \(\mathcal{C}_{B_1 B_2}\text{,}\) that should complete the proof that \(\mathcal{C}_{B_1 B_2}\) is a valid category.
Knowing \(\mathcal{C}_{B_1 B_2}\) is a category, what should the terminal object look like? Per definition, a terminal object \(T\) should have the property that for every object \(X\) in \(\mathcal{C}_{B_1 B_2}\text{,}\) there is exactly one map \(X \xrightarrow{\tau} T\text{.}\) As an object in \(\mathcal{C}_{B_1 B_2}\text{,}\) the terminal object \(T\) must be accompanied by a pair of maps \(T \xrightarrow{\tau_1} B_1\) and \(T \xrightarrow{\tau_2} B_1\) such that \(\tau_1 \tau = \phi_1\) and \(\tau_2 \tau = \phi_2\) where \(\phi_1,\phi_2\) are the respective pair of maps associated with \(X\text{.}\)
Since every object has an identity map, this rule must also apply to \(T\text{.}\) Since any \(X \rightarrow T\) is unique, then the uniqueness of \(T \rightarrow T\) implies it could only be the map \(1_T\text{.}\) Clearly \(1_T\) satisfies \(\tau_1 1_T = \tau_1\) and \(\tau_2 1_T = \tau_2\text{.}\)
Now suppose we have a \(\mathcal{C}\)-map \(B_1 \xrightarrow{\beta} T\text{,}\) which we should by the definition of terminal object. In order for this map to be a map in \(\mathcal{C}_{B_1 B_2}\text{,}\) we’d need a pair of maps \(B_1 \xrightarrow{\beta_1} B_1\) and \(B_2 \xrightarrow{\beta_2} B_2\) which preserve the structure of the following diagram:
These maps need to preserve the structure of the relations \(\tau_1 \beta = \beta_1\) and \(\tau_2 \beta = \beta_2\text{.}\) Since \(\beta \circ \tau_1\) is a map from \(T \rightarrow T\text{,}\) of which there is only one, we’re forced to conclude that \(\beta \circ \tau_1 = 1_T\text{.}\) Precomposing our structure preserving relations with \(\tau_1\) gives us:
\begin{equation*}
\tau_1 \beta \tau_1 = \tau_1 1_T = \tau_1 = \beta_1 \tau_1
\end{equation*}
\begin{equation*}
\tau_2 \beta \tau_1 = \tau_2 1_T = \tau_2 = \beta_2 \tau_1
\end{equation*}
If we take \(\tau_2 = \beta_2 \tau_1\) and precompose with \(\beta\) again, we get \(\tau_2 \beta = \beta_2 \tau_1 \beta\) which simplifies to \(\beta_2 = \beta_2 \beta_1\) whichs implies that \(\beta_1 = 1_{B_1} = \tau_1 \circ \beta\text{.}\) It would also follow that \(\beta_2\) is uniquely determined by the sequence of maps \(B_1 \xrightarrow{\beta} T \xrightarrow{\tau_2} B_2\text{.}\) Essentially, since the objects \(T,B_1,B_2\) are all isomorphic to each other in \(\mathcal{C}\) we can use the uniqueness of the maps there to guarantee the uniqueness of our maps in \(\mathcal{C}_{B_1 B_2}\text{.}\)
I’m thinking that the idea here is that there is not just a bijection between the objects \(X\) and \(T\text{,}\) but one between the pairs of maps \(\langle \phi_1, \phi_2 \rangle\) and \(\langle \tau_1, \tau_2 \rangle\) themselves. Consequently, any bijection between \(\boxed{P,\pi_1,\pi_2} \leftrightarrows \boxed{T,\tau_1,\tau_2}\) automatically defines an unique bijection \(\boxed{X,\phi_1,\phi_2} \leftrightarrows \boxed{P,\pi_1,\pi_2}\) through composition.